As I noted yesterday (recall), I read recently Liberalism and the Empire: three essays (1900) by Francis W. Hirst, Gilbert Murray, and J. L. Hammond. This collection is clearly building on, and in the same intellectual orbit as, J.A. Hobson’s (1900) War in South Africa and anticipates many of the themes of Hobson’s (1902) Imperialism: A Study.
Today my focus is on Gilbert Murray’s middle essay, “The exploitation of inferior races in ancient and modern times: an Imperial labor question, with a historical parallel.” When he published his piece, the Australia born Gilbert Murray (1866 – 1957) had just resigned his professorship of Greek at the University of Glasgow. A few years later he became the Regius Professor of Greek at the University of Oxford. His classical learning is rather important to the essay because it involves a comparison between how the Greeks and Romans massacred, colonized, and enslaved with more modern counterparts (especially the English in South Africa and Australia).
Murray introduces the theme of his essay as follows:
Murray, thus, aims to avoid the moralizing (“unpractical aversion”) of the generous cosmopolitan few and the nationalist self-aggrandizement of the many. Interestingly enough, his own ‘purely scientific spirit’ is compatible with moral apprehension of the facts (‘evils’). This evaluative scientific spirit permeates the work. Since Murray denies he will offer detailed remedies, he implies he wishes to offer a kind of unvarnished understanding. He sticks to that stance almost until the end.
And, yet, a sensitive reader may well wonder about the title’s coupling of ‘exploitation’ with ‘inferior races.’ He doesn’t define these terms at the start of the paper, but by the by. In the case of ‘exploitation’ and, as we’ll see, ‘inferiority,’ Aristotle is Murray’s partial lodestone. I quote (albeit having substituted away the N-word):
The answer, of course, is that Aristotle was not afraid of the word 'slave,' and used it far more lightly and freely than we care to do. His own admirable definition of the term as 'a live tool' seems to cover exactly the same ground as our word 'exploit.' In so far as a person is 'exploited' — that is, in so far as he is used for another's interest without any regard for his own — he is, according to Aristotle, a slave. The ancients would certainly have regarded not only the enforced labour of the Matabele, but the ordinary indentured labour of ['Africans’] in Kimberley, Kanakas in Queens-land, and coolies in India, Demerara, Fiji, and the like, as slave labour. (p. 134) [Cf. Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics 1161b and Politics 1253b).
Murray’s main underlying point is that while the British empire may have abolished slavery de jure, the practice still exists on a massive scale. The empire is exploitative in character. For, our purposes it is interesting that for Murray there is a kind of commensurability between the vocabulary of modern social science (‘exploit’) and Ancient philosophy (to be used as a ‘slave’).
As an aside, Murray had introduced this passage with the claim that “many, perhaps most, Greek philosophers from the fifth century B.C. onwards condemned the institution of slavery in itself as 'contrary to nature.’ Some of the democratic sophists, like Alcidamas, proposed its actual abolition.” (p. 133) The mention of Alcidamas’ stance is prima facie a bit puzzling because Murray had intimated he would offer no such reform program. I return to that below.
Be that as it may, this commensurability also seems to be present in his vocabulary of superiority/inferiority. I quote:
So, for Murray it is fairly typical that more powerful peoples tend to abuse those in their power and become morally worse doing so. While the massacres and “cruelties perpetrated by white men upon coloured men,” (p. 152) are not unexpected given the great power difference, they exhibit the moral corruption of the English and other imperialist nations. As he puts it “Let no one delude himself with the fancy that, though the German Dr. Peters may flog his concubines to death, though Frenchmen in the New Hebrides may twist the flesh off their servants' backs with pincers, though our own newspapers may revel in reported horrors from the old Transvaal or the Congo Free State, Englishmen, Scotchmen, and Irish men are quite of another breed.” (p. 153) It is a fact of nature that typically all imperial rulers become moral monsters.
For Murray, then, Aristotle is right that there is a natural hierarchy among kinds of men, even if the hierarchy itself can be partially diminished and adjusted to some degree. He makes this much more explicit near the conclusion of his essay which shades into exhortation:
The powerful have duties to the powerless. So, let’s call this a kind of ‘benevolent racism.’ Now, in the nineteenth century such benevolent racism justified empire as a civilizing project.
But, unlike (say) J.S. Mill, for Murray this benevolence is not expressed or furthered by such a civilizing mission. Rather, duty involves abandonment of empire: “If ever in the lifetime of the world a duty has been laid upon a nation, a great and manifest obligation lies on us towards our subject-peoples, the duty of endeavouring by strenuous and honest sympathy, justice, and even magnanimity, to obliterate our cruel conquests, and justify our world-wide usurpation.” (p. 157) In the final sentence of the essay, Murray quotes Burke — in a passage highlighted by John Morley’s study — to emphasize this very point: “On the way in which we respond to that call of duty, more than on any other single criterion, depends the verdict that history must pass upon us, whether to proclaim us the greatest and most beneficent of nations, or merely to dismiss us as one more group in the long dark flight of transient and unprofitable conquerors, ‘birds of prey and of passage,’ at whose final disappearance Humanity will raise her bent head and utter a sigh of relief.” (p. 157)
We’re now in a position to understand Murray’s position. It’s indeed the case that he offers (recall) “no detailed remedies” for the evils he diagnoses. But while accepting Aristotle’s diagnosis of the human condition, he thinks Alcidamas does point in the right programmatic (first best) direction: abandon empire or we will become human monsters.
In fact, according to Murray, there is a second-best alternative that he expects to be equally unpopular. This is the civilization mission (which I have associated with Mill above, and which Murray will associate with old-fashioned idealists below). However, the point of that mission would be not beneficence, but (rather) enlightened self-interest:
That is to say, according to Murray the English empire is doomed to fall because when it will need defending in a time of dire emergency its subject nations will not be allied, self-governing nations, but rather break (now quoting Gibbon) “their chains, and…revenge the injuries and the disgrace of their cruel servitude.”
Murray, not unlike Hobson, is clearly a racist and an anti-imperialist. But unlike Hobson, who advocated supra-national federalism among settler-colonists and the world’s ‘superior’ races, Murray thought (not unlike his fellow-essayists, Hirst and Hammond) that the best policy would be imperial retreat, a wealthy ‘little England’ in the tradition of Cobden and Bright. But, unusually, he thought the second-best policy would be to federate with subject-populations so as to avoid imperial decline. So, somewhat oddly, while Murray’s vocabulary is Aristotelian, the political theory is Machiavelli’s.