General readers will recall that I have been blogging about Bertrand Russell’s (1916). Principles of Social Reconstruction that originated in a series of public lectures. (Also known in America as Why Men Fight.) In previous posts I have tried to take the work on its own terms. But while I have admiration for Russell’s courage to oppose war during wartime (and the work is significant anticipation of the themes of Marriage and Morals), my general estimation of these essays is that they are very uneven.
However, there is a reason to be very interested in the collection. And that’s because it reflects Russell’s social views while he is co-inventing analytic philosophy not the least enduring features of its methodology (as Alexander Klein has emphasized). It’s a decade after “On Denoting,” and only a few years after he published Problems of Philosophy, Principia Mathematica, and Our Knowledge of the External World. And shortly thereafter he will publish Mysticism and Logic and Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy. Today’s post links Russell’s meta-philosophical views to his scientific philosophy and social theory.
While the titles of the collection’s final two essays — “Religion and the Churches” (essay 7) and “What Can We Do” (essay 8) — suggest otherwise, they are intimately connected. Chapter 7 alerts us to the idea that there is a need to renew spirit (which alongside mind and instinct is one of the three key principles of social life that need to be balanced against each other—and Russel emphasizes the need to create “harmony between mind and instinct” (p. 154)). Russell’s account of the life of spirit includes one of his most lyrical passages; so I quote in full:
For Russell it is pretty obvious that existing churches are becoming incapable of reanimating the life of spirit. Before long he expects that “it will be possible for a new organic society and a new inner synthesis to take place which the Church held for a thousand years.” ((pp. 138-9) Much of the seventh essay hints at the Nietzschean idea (familiar also from Carnap and Parfit later) that Russell views himself as a philosopher of the future with a life-affirming philosophy. As he puts in the eight chapter, “The world has need of a philosophy, or a religion, which will promote life.” (p. 168)
In this seventh essay, one of Russell’s regulative ideas is that “the life of the mind, although supremely excellent in itself, cannot bring health into the life of instinct, except when it results in a not too difficult outlet for the instinct of creation.” (p. 148) He rejects, for example, the praiseworthy attempts by “vitalism, futurism, pragmatism, and the various other philosophies which advertise themselves as vigorous and virile.” They all fail because they subordinate “thought to instinct, a refusal to allow thought to achieve its own ideal.” For Russell, “thought must achieve its full growth before a reconciliation with instinct is attempted.” (p. 148) Or as he puts it in the next essay, “what integrates an individual life is a consistent creative purpose or unconscious direction.” (p. 158) So, Russell invites his reader into thinking that he has an alternative philosophical program that can provide such integration.
In chapter 8, Russell explains more concretely what he has in mind:
Russell discusses a number of episodes of moral progress which originate in small groups that eventually are seen to be ahead of the times. The underlying idea can be traced back to his godfather, Mill (and, of course, Machiavelli’s ‘new prince’ or the Christian apostles), who embraces an idea of moral progress that is rooted in the activities of a moral elite/avant-garde. “The power of thought, in the long run, is greater than any other human power.” (p. 156; Mill’s own feminism is offered as one example.) Russell himself may well have thought of Bloomsbury, although he explicitly mentions Labour.
Being part of a moral elite entails hardship and isolation:
In context, Russell also hints at his inspiration. As he writes, “the right kind of thought is rare and difficult,” (p. 156)* and this evokes the closing lines of Spinoza’s Ethics. This is indeed the philosophy that promotes “life.” As he puts it a few pages down:
In order to promote life it is necessary to value something other than mere life. Life devoted only to life is animal without any real human value, incapable of preserving men permanently from weariness and the feeling that all is vanity. If life is to be fully human it must serve some end which seems, in some sense, outside human life, some end which is impersonal and above mankind, such as God or truth or beauty. Those who best promote life do not have life for their purpose. They aim rather at what seems like a gradual incarnation, a bringing into our human existence of something eternal, something that appears to imagination to live in a heaven remote from strife and failure and the devouring jaws of Time. Contact with this eternal world—even if it be only a world of our imagining—brings a strength and a fundamental peace which cannot be wholly destroyed by the struggles and apparent failures of our temporal life. It is this happy contemplation of what is eternal that Spinoza calls the intellectual love of God. To those who have once known it, it is the key of wisdom. (pp. 168-169; emphasis added)
What’s peculiar about this passage is that while evoking Spinoza, Russell explicitly deviates from Spinoza’s own way to generate intellectual love of God. For, Spinoza would deny that one has genuine contact with the eternal world if it is a world of our imagining (and, anticipating Nietzsche, Spinoza would deny willing a fiction is itself life-affirming).
Now, if I understand Russell correctly in these two essays, he is not himself claiming that he has a fully worked out philosophy that can generate a life-affirming spirit. Rather — and he explicitly compares this with Augustine’s publication of City of God after the sack of Rome (p. 170) — he thinks he can provide a “new hope.” So, I take him to be claiming that the happy contemplation of an imperfect world of our imagining may be prefatory to the birth or generation of something eternal.
Russell here evokes an important passage (that figured in one of my first attempts at blogging (here) at NewAPPS in conversation with Jeff Bell) from “On Scientific Method in Philosophy” (1914) [in Mysticism and Logic] that helps explain what he has in mind:
So, in 1914 Russell makes a fairly sharp distinction between practice and theory. And Spinoza’s work is held up as the kind of thinking that can animate practice. Russell implies here that his own scientific philosophy has no impact on “improvement of human life.” Of course, as Alexander Klein has argued, Russell’s meta-philosophy embraces the scientific temper with an “antinationalistic agenda.”
As I have noted before, this anti-nationalism is also visible in the 1916 lectures/collection that is my present focus. For Russell associates nationalism with a zero-sum imperialist mentality:
The supreme principle, both in politics and in private life, should be to promote all that is creative, and so to diminish the impulses and desires that center round possession. The State at present is very largely an embodiment of possessive impulses: internally, it protects the rich against the poor; externally, it uses force for the exploitation of inferior races, and for competition with other States. (p. 163; emphasis in original
As I have already noted in my discussion of Russell’s treatment of eugenics (here), it is pretty clear that in 1916 Russell embraces natural inequality of populations. So even though Russell is against exploiting them, he thinks there are inferior races. Such ‘benevolent racism’ stance is not uncommon among anti-imperialists of the age—we also see it among some liberals like Hobson and (recall) the classicist Gilbert Murray.
Be that as it may, Spinoza matters to Russell because he is treated as pointing toward a non-zero-plus orientation toward our impulses and desires and to promote a species of creativity. We might say, then, that in Russell of this period, Spinoza’s neo-Stoicism is elevated at the expense of Spinoza’s own defense of property rights and nationalism.
But unlike in 1914, Russell does not separate practice from theory sharply in 1916. For he hints that a neo-Spinozist philosophy that promotes the supreme principle does have a connection with his own more scientific philosophy. For, according to Russell, the most creative life is actually the life of science, “The men of science, who have less difficulty than any others in finding an outlet for creativeness, are the happiest of intelligent men in the modern world, since their creative activity affords full satisfaction to mind and spirit as well as to the instinct of creation.” (p. 147) Spinozism promotes a creative life; and, in the modern world, that means turning to science.
The crucial point is hinted at obliquely in the following sentence: “In them a beginning is to be seen of the new way of life which is to be sought; in their happiness we may perhaps find the germ of a future happiness for all mankind.” (p. 147, emphasis added.) Is this germ supposed to blossom with the aid of a scientific philosophy?
*Russell continues, “but it is not impotent.” Throughout these essays, Russell’s anxiety about manhood and virility are lurking not far under the surface. I leave it to another to interpret the significance of this.